PDA

View Full Version : What Do We Mean by ‘Freedom’?



thedrifter
07-25-05, 02:03 PM
What Do We Mean by ‘Freedom’?
Written by Brian Melton
Monday, July 25, 2005

“They have been at a great feast of languages, and stolen the scraps.”

- Shakespeare, Love’s Labour Lost

Britain has just been hit by another wave of bombings. A natural result of this sort of thing is fear and a desire to make certain attacks don’t happen again. People demand restrictive measures designed with safety in mind. As a result, liberal activists, university professors, and various lobbies take up a chant that I am certain will sound quite familiar to your ears. It goes something like this:

Person A: We need to do something to secure our borders and protect our people. Perhaps we should start checking people who come into the country, or watching immigration. If not, we won’t be a free country for long.

Person B: You {insert derogatory expletive of choice here} are so hypocritical! You say you believe in “freedom” and then at the first breath of danger you take it all back. What’s more, you go around forcing your disgusting morality on everyone! That’s the exact opposite of freedom.

What is very important to note, is that this argument applies to just about any liberal cause under the sun, not just (mostly) unintentionally aiding and abetting terrorists. The same attack crops up whenever someone brings up a view on homosexuality, abortion, welfare, etc. that a liberal doesn’t particularly care to hear.

I myself have heard this more times than I care to count. The point of the exercise, from the liberal perspective, is to a: make Person A feel guilty over having brought up principles that contradict Person B’s, and b: to “demonstrate” that Person A has somehow morally disqualified his or herself from being able to speak on that subject again. The only way to come out from under this ban is to grovel at the feet of a liberal cause.

Well, I for one have finally had it, and I think its time to clear the philosophical air a bit. What’s actually happening in the above situation is yet another semantic game, one that conservatives and Christians have let liberals get away with for far too long.

The real issue at hand is what freedom really means.

In modern America, we have two definitions for the same word, one of them older and more philosophically consistent than the other. The more respectable and practical definition of freedom is that it is the right to choose between every right--or at least morally neutral--thing.

According to this definition, there is right, there is wrong, and human beings understand morality to the point that they can intelligently choose right over wrong. If a thing is wrong (such as making child pornography or committing rape or murder), we never have a “right” to choose it (though we may have the power to do so). In fact, governments and laws are set up to prevent people from choosing wrong things, and to punish those that have. Everything else, from the morally neutral to the morally good, is fair game for people to exercise their freedom upon. This covers toothpaste to education to where they live to where they work to where they worship and anything that falls in between.

The newer, less consistent definition of freedom comes to us from the now popularized postmodern movement. The very essence of PM is relativism, an outflow of naturalism where there is no settled norm for anything, especially morals. Everything is reduced to mere preference and personal opinion.

So, if there is no right or wrong, then freedom means the right choose between all things, regardless of any alleged moral consequences. Usually there is a “so long as it doesn’t hurt anyone” rider attached to it, but anyone who can think past the end of his or her nose will see that there isn’t a single reason why an action shouldn’t hurt anyone, as long as the perpetrator can get away with it. After all, who says there’s something wrong about hurting someone else?

What we have in the hypothetical conversation above is a bit of semantical sleight of hand. The original speaker, Person A, has made a statement that presumes the first, more reliable definition of freedom. To Person A, there is nothing inherently contradictory about saying that a group of people does not have the freedom to do a thing, so long as that thing is clearly wrong (such as allowing murdering terrorist into a country). The question for Person A is this: “Does the action in question stand the test of morality?” If so, then people are free to pursue it, if not, then it is no more hypocritical to suggest that someone be prevented from “choosing” it than to say that pedophilia should be illegal. Person B may not like the conclusion that Person A reaches, but Person A isn’t being hypocritical in the least.

The hypocrisy is actually imposed from without, by Person B. Person B uses exactly the same language as Person A, but surreptitiously (though not always consciously) changes the meaning of the word “freedom” radically, from the old to the new. If allowed to get away with this substitution, Person B will have “proved” Person A to be both a moron and a hypocrite.

How should one respond in a situation like this? Don’t let the switch take place. The real question at hand is which definition of “freedom” is right, and why.

It should be obvious that the modern secularist definition must fall apart at the merest breath of either critical analysis or practical application. There are some acts, such as those mentioned above, that every sane person believes is wrong. They also believe that people should be prevented from committing such acts, if at all possible. Successfully precluding an act means it is no longer a choice. If we try to preclude all occurrences, we have implicitly acknowledged that act is “wrong” whatever philosophical garbage we may spout.

Even the fact that they believe that “no one should be hurt” by an action implies that they believe at least one thing is “right.” And if that is “right,” then violating it must be “wrong.” Also, many relativists are quite happy to live with their philosophy, but only until it comes home to roost. After an “insurgent” has blown their loved ones to tiny bits while making a “political statement,” people tend to see things differently.

Note that this does not, in itself prove anything beyond the fact that the liberal approach to “freedom,” well intentioned though it may be, does not reflect reality. Everyone should be “free,” but some ideologies and causes (such as the ones they champion) are more “free” than others. Homosexuals are free to do as they like in public, but Christian ministers could face prosecution for saying that homosexuality is wrong.

No one should take this op-ed to mean that I think any government should be given a blank check to “protect” its citizens by trampling over all of their legitimate, God-given rights. But we should also be careful to make sure that the “rights” in question have not recently been created using a completely asinine definition of “freedom” that is as meaningless as it is self-refuting. Given the literal life and death issues we face, sensible people, both in Britain and the United States, must train themselves to take the conversation up a notch or two, to get through guilt trip of smoke and mirrors, and at the real questions behind it all. It is there that we hold all the aces.

About the Writer: Brian Melton is an assistant professor of history at Liberty University. Brian receives e-mail at bmelton@liberty.edu.

Ellie

tbruyle5
07-25-05, 10:46 PM
Very well said!!!:yes: :yes: